Skip to content

The work developed from 2015 onward, and is protected by BONO and international copyright laws.

 

(Analogue) Film is light-stamped in material time. Material is a form of time.

 

Trânsito, 2015 – 2018, Oslo, Norway, analogue photography. The artwork delves into the “reality as stratification of surfaces” through Perniola’s concept of transit.* From this work, limited edition prints, public art installations, and material applications such as wall coverings, mosaics, metal, acrylic and custom panels, facades, projections, textile and garments, and product applications with Kinetic Facades, Artaic Custom Mosaic Tiles, Equitone Fiber Cement Facade, Acrylic or Textile Panels, Metal with substrate installation systems, and Projections follow the images. *Research paper follows the presentation. Contact:  mariammanart@icloud.com Download: Transito PDF, Transito Realizations

 

An iridescent color palette reminiscent of oil and visual surface of water joins in the imaginary realm as a means to consider the implausible, as possible, to create new intelligence defying previous assumed knowledge or reason. Trânsito reflects the heavens in the gentle surface ripples, looking at phenomenological discourses in painting and photography through the ethics of resource usage in technocratic times. The granularity of the analogue, chemical process in photography translated into digitally scalable pixels are emphasized to draw attention to the passage of movement in stillness, paradoxically making viewers feel as if they are moving while standing still. Developed alongside Teknovisuell Experience on the degradation of technology through repetition to find how the perceived problem presents the solution based on distances in viewing. The physiology and psychology of the body viewing, and mechanical apparatus of photography are thus focused on sensorial memories of beauty, love, reason, and enlightenment. Trânsito is part of Virtual Material body of work, exploiting photography while engaging in phenomenological subjects with water, stones, forests, technology, vision, body, perception, ethics. The Virtual Material body of work includes: Trânsito, Teknovisuell Experience, Sonidos, Fleuressence, Relatively Dimensional Still-Life, 1919 in 2017, videos, installations, as prints, projections, wall coverings, acrylic prints, garments. Contact: mariammanart@icloud.com

 

 

The series was created at Tjuvholmen, looking toward Oslofjord. Norway is known for nature as well as oil extraction, leading the technology in making sure the process is clean and effective. The social dilemma and admirable work for safe resources usage is well known both within and beyond the borders. The images are framed with the curiosity to gain insight into the convergence of resources and technology as the way through time. Alongside my personal perspective that quiet joy heals, the images were exhibited three-years after the exposures were made, at Vérité, in Oslo, Norway. Vérité, French for “the truth” realized the imaginary confluence water and oil through a relationship with technological development.

Oil and water as subject of cognitive and geological polarisation, presents the work as an allegorical element for making history with technology. The reference to water as a reflective, rippling surface invites imagination of the etheric by reflecting the sky. Iridescent colors, abstract forms, and enhanced film granulation create a sense of movement within the viewers. Instead of feeling standing still, the reality of subtle forces can be remembered and accessed through viewing the Trânsito artwork.

 

Inspired by Umberto Eco‘s ideas on late modernity, in Chronicles of a Liquid Society, the ways images are read as inverses within embodied cognitive connections, are realized within the viewer as malleable surfaces related to memory. The viewing distances engage viewers’ senses (of stillness and movement) and of the ways appearances can obfuscate and reveal, expand or contract.

 

Making the conceptually impossible, possible always comes with sacrifice and costs that must be deeply considered. Philosophically, the predetermined cost of the digitization of life itself poses a paradox on notions of intelligence. Ideas and even good intentions can be dangerous, creating larger issues from relative abundance. Therefore the references in the work maintain the relationship to reality. They are carefully framed to generate a sense of acceptance but not complicit compliance. The viewer is realized as the generative agent in self-understanding and action. From the root of serenity and beauty, humans subjectivity moves differently than from motives of confusion or conflation.

 

Appearance is often cognitively accepted as not the thing itself and yet the awareness of subconscious influences through the flood of images humanity is faced with today. The effects on the afferent nervous system of the body invites viewers into deeper contemplation. In this way Appearances, while often considered superficial or vain, are understood as being within the body. In this way we can relate to the real as a means to reflect on depth from within. The afferent nervous system of the body functions inwardly. Therefore this work is aimed to instead of excite, but calm and inspire contemplation on notions of subjectivity, resources, dominance, supremacy, simpatico, depth and surface.

 

Discernment between the surface and the depth, reaches an overlap through the imaginary, an in this series, the images which vary subtly, inviting quiet within the viewer. From this deep well of quiet, fantastic colours of resplendence invites awareness. In these works the notions of subjectivity, resources, dominance, supremacy, simpatico, depth and surface come into question. The apparatus of both photography and human sight are realized in a format evoking stillness and movement. Serenity becomes eery, beauty becomes hypnotic, and digital enhancements of film emulsions remind viewers of the symbolism of sand and time through granularity and smoothness. The iridescent wave forms of Oslofjord invite reflection on the relationship humans have with water, imagination, vision, and the sacred. In the image, fantasy can appear real and possible: oil and water mixing, the mutability in reflection, the eternal motive to capture and share. The Trânsito series reaches to understand Eros and technology in a pragmatic way. These questions about vision, nature and technology are about our relationships with life. The viewing distances engage viewers’ senses (of stillness and movement) and of the ways appearances can obfuscate and reveal, expand or contract.

 

The ethics of water, mineral resources, labor and other sacrifices are well documented to have irreversible costs. Through the apparatus of photography and vision, discernment between serenity and subjugation, the hypnotic and active invite openness instead of drawn conclusions. The digital enhancement of the film emulsions evoke granularity of sand, often symbolized relative to time.

 

The original film exposures of the iridescent wave forms appear considerably different than the works presented here. The complete series is to invite reflection on the relationship humans have with water, imagination, vision, and the sacred. By way of the the image, fantasy can appear real and possible: oil and water mixing, the mutability in reflection, the eternal motive to capture and share. The Trânsito series invites understandings of Eros and effects of screens and technology in a pragmatic way. Our human relationships with the connection to life and each other is what is at stake. Therefore

 

Furthermore, I learned through making these works as well as many others, I understand the field of viewing as holographic and, at least, metaphorically containing woven elements. What is seen is woven by the earth’s spinning, gravity, space, and the time runs through all these as well as our bodies. Therefore the images are also fibers of being, and forever altered the future of my work with the camera. Tactility relates to the senses, and the ability for art to open up the senses and invite remembering, feeling, moving into serenity and beauty brings me continued motivation to realise these works in new mediums and installed at several sites.

 

 

EXHIBITIONS AND PRODUCT MOCK-UPS

Photography: Bjørnar Brende Smestad/@bjornarsmestad
Model: Ida T/@idambt
Artist: Mari Amman/@mariammanstudio
AD: Rudy Wolff/@rudy_wolff

Photography: Bjørnar Brende Smestad/@bjornarsmestad
Model: Ida T/@idambt
Artist: Mari Amman/@mariammanstudio
AD: Rudy Wolff/@rudy_wolff

 

Reality as Stratification of Surfaces: The Concept of Transit in Perniola’s Philosophy

Publication Date: September 2, 2018, Sep 8, 2024
by: Enea Bianchi

Retrieved from: The European Journal of Psychoanalysis

https://www.journal-psychoanalysis.eu/articles/reality-as-stratification-of-surfaces-the-concept-of-transit-in-perniolas-philosophy-2/

summary

The aim of this paper is to show in what terms reality can be considered as a stratification of surfaces by developing Mario Perniola’s philosophy of transit. The first part will deal with the etymology of the word transit, in order to explain its meanings and uses. As it will be clarified, the development of the notion of transit goes together with the conception of reality as deep in the sense of full, available, rich, as the realm of “difference” and “enigmas”. The second part will explain the particular conception of temporality implied in the transit. Together with Perniola’s analysis, Nietzschean and Deleuzian reflections about “amor fati” and “eternal return” will be further explored. This concept is crucial to understand not only Perniola’s overall philosophy by clarifying his position against postmodern thinkers; it also provides a theoretical framework from which the task and the challenge of the philosopher in the contemporary world emerge.

 

reality as stratification of surfaces

The objective of this section is twofold. On the one hand it will clarify the notion of transit, to which the Italian writer and philosopher Mario Perniola devoted the volume Transiti. Come si va dallo stesso allo stesso (Transits. How to go from same to same); on the other hand, it will show the peculiar revaluation of the notion of depth developed by Perniola. In fact, according to the Italian philosopher, among the postmodern thinkers there is a commonplace for which the concept of depth belongs to metaphysics (object of criticism by postmodernism), and because of this it is refused and rejected. On the contrary, Perniola argues that depth has other significant meanings, not taken into account by postmodern theory, that enable us to rehabilitate this notion. As will be made clearer further on, Perniola’s considerations over the concept of depth can help better understand the notion of transit. At the end of the paper, it will be clear why Perniola understands reality as a stratification of surfaces.

 

The word ‘transit’ comes from the Latin transitus, meaning “passage”, “transfer”, “transition”, which also refers to the verb transeo, “to go across”, “to pass through”, “to transform”. Different uses of this term have arisen from its Latin etymology: in its daily usage, “transit” can mean carrying people from one place to another, or passing through a place; philosophically speaking, different conceptual declinations are involved. On the one hand, the idea of transit refers to a certain specific literature based on the transience of life – that is, on the precariousness and the shortness of our earthly passage. A telling example of this literature is expressed by Asai Ry? in the novel Ukiyo Monogatari (Tales of the Floating World), written in 1661: living only for the moment, savouring the moon, the snow, the cherry blossoms, and the maple leaves, singing songs, drinking sake, and diverting oneself just in floating, unconcerned by the prospect of imminent poverty, buoyant and carefree, like a gourd carried along with the river current: this is what we call ukiyo (qtd. in Hickman 6) Perniola’s philosophy takes a different direction on the concept of transit. The first to dwell on the nature of transit in Western tradition, according to Perniola, was Heraclitus, for whom the things of the world share the essential characteristic of the so-called enantiodromia—the coincidence of opposites. This implies considering every reality as always-becoming, as everything is susceptible to turn into its opposite. For instance, the famous aphorism, “You cannot not step twice into the same river,” implies that one may apparently be immersing oneself into those same waters, yet at the same time the river flows on and thus changes unceasingly. This is “at once a process of passing from the same to the same and the persistence of what is in itself different” (Perniola,Enigmas 17). Enantiodromia and transit share a fundamental feature, namely they imply the atopic character of every reality. The adjective atopic, from Greek atopos, both means “a-topos” (“devoid of a place”; “placelessness”) and “singular”, “unusual”, “unclassifiable”. The very history of philosophy, for Perniola, can be understood through this concept. Why many philosophers, from Thales to Socrates, Boethius, Giordano Bruno and Heidegger, were denigrated, hated or persecuted? Because of the “atopic nature of philosophy” itself: “the hatred of philosophy has deep roots, unmentionable motivations, surprising manifestations: what actually animates it is the philosopher’s avoidance of a definitive collocation, his/her staying in transit” (Perniola, Transiti2). The philosopher, according to this view, does not follow any utopia or topicality but is oriented toward the atopia. These three terms share the same Greek etymological origin, namely the word “topos” (place). However, where utopia means “no-place”, and topical means “actual” in the sense of a “deposit of stereotypes” (Perniola, Transiti2), only atopia, according to Perniola, has a privileged relationship of affinity with reality. The utopia is considered by Perniola as a non-existing representation that revolves around an ideal community or society only imagined, without a proper consistence and significance: a “motionless and perfect republic of the spirit” (7); on the other hand, the topical is that particular, ordinary dimension of thinking, which dissolves reality in the ephemeral actuality. In contrast with these two notions, Perniola sees philosophy as that particular and unique kind of thought that can account for reality, understood as multi-layered and enigmatic. Here reality is used in a broad sense because Perniola develops the transit as a wide-ranging and multifaceted notion: from an “erotic transit” (69-83), to a “transit ritual” (189-203), from a “telematic transit” (217-229) to an “artistic transit” (150-158). Even if at first glance the subtitle of Transiti (“How to go from the same to the same”) seems to imply a sterile movement terminating with the state of a certain thing or phenomenon remaining unchanged, the actual meaning is the opposite, namely the flourishing of difference within each reality: to think of the richness of changes implicit in the same phenomenon, at the same time, in the same reality. Not to claim that A is equal to B, C, D […] and ultimately, that one thing is as any other—but indeed to show that B, C, D […] can derive from A through minimum distinctions, subtle slips, imperceptible declinations. (Transiti1)

 

To clarify this passage, it is necessary to understand the re-evaluation of the concept of depth developed by Perniola. In an article devoted to this concept (“Per una rivalutazione della nozione di profondità”), Perniola argues against the postmodern conception of depth and praises the idea of “depth as stratification”, as will be clarified further on. In Ihab Hassan’s table of differences between modernism and postmodernism, Perniola highlights the opposition between “depth”, which falls under modernism, and “surface”, belonging to postmodernism. The postmodern opposition, according to Hassan, lies between cause, substance, truth, origin, metaphysic, on one side, and, on the other, flexibility, lightness, ephemerality. The weakness of this dichotomy, according to Perniola, can be seen in the undue match between depth and metaphysics. Postmodern thinkers, in their crusade against every concept gravitating around the notion of metaphysics, have also wrongly addressed their critique over “depth”. Hassan’s table is a clear example of this perspective, in which there is a direct link between these two notions. This inclusion, for Perniola, misleads the very concept of depth, as will be made clearer shortly.

 

In order to develop his perspective, Perniola addresses the semantic expansions of the words profundus and báthos (respectively Latin and Greek terms for depth) as the English word “depth” has its semantic roots in the Indo-European dheu-b, from which the Latin word fundus originated. Pro-fundus– “far [is] the bottom” – had two principal meanings: in the Roman age it used to indicate something immeasurable, without an end, in a pejorative and negative sense (for instance:profunda avaritia, deep avarice). With the advent of Christianity, and particularly with the works of Augustine of Hippo, it shifted to a positive connotation. In fact, even though indicating the boundless depth of human sins, at the same time it implied its overturning, namely the salvation through God’s love: “the soul is deep not only because it reproduces in itself the abyss of sin, but especially because in that abyss the premises for its redemption are already present” (Perniola, “Per una rivalutazione” 97).

 

The Greek word báthos, in its archaic use, expressed the idea of fullness and richness, both physically (the deep sea) and metaphorically (a deep affect, sentiment or thought). Philosophically, Perniola quotes Diogenes Laertius who referred to Heraclitus as a “sea-diver” who immerses himself into the depths of thought. From Plato on, Perniola continues, a decisive turning point occurred. True knowledge started to be conceived as an ascent to the hyperuranium and not a descent into the profound and earthly world. Báthos became pejorative and hypselós (the Greek word for “sublime”) emerged. This spiritualistic element marginalized the semantic spectrum of depth (báthos). An example of how báthos lost its importance by acquiring negative meanings can be seen in Neoplatonism. Indeed, the father of Neoplatonism, Plotinus, considers “depth” the sinful things of the world (matter, bodies…) whereas, on the contrary, the spirit, the soul and the ideal can be reached only through a vertical movement of transcendence.

 

Perniola’s aim is to re-evaluate the notion of depth by avoiding the postmodern commonplace for which “depth” is closely related to interiority, authenticity, truth and eventually metaphysics. By showing the etymological uses of the words profundus and bátho she reaches the conclusion that the spiritual element (transcendence, totality, absolute) is not necessarily present in the notion of depth. As the Greek báthos and the Roman’s first use of profundus indicate, these terms used to have an earthly connotation and not a transcendent one. For Perniola, in addition, the Augustinian conception of depth should not be considered spiritualistic but dialectic, as it consists in the awareness that something is deep when it is susceptible of changing into its opposite. Thus, when postmodern thinkers argue against the notion of depth, they wrongly include it within the wide range of metaphysical concepts, by erroneously taking for granted that depth means transcendence and ultimately metaphysics. This is the reason why Perniola disengages from postmodern critique by re-evaluating the very notion of depth within the perspective of the transit. The development of the concept of transit goes together with the conception of reality as deep in the sense of full, available, rich—and not deep because transcendent, as postmodern thought incorrectly claims.Reality, according to this view, is paradoxically made of deep surfaces: This possibility opens up when I think depth as a stratification of surfaces, that means something full, instead of empty. This idea seems to me particularly close to archaeological depth, in which what is ancient emerges layer after layer, surface after surface, in the context of a philosophical perspective that eliminates emptiness. (“Per una rivalutazione” 95)

 

Surface layers because nothing appears under the surface itself. In other words, there is not a dualism between an interior which is covered by an exterior. On the contrary it is all surfaces and exteriority. This is why Perniola argues that “philosophizing is like peeling an onion” (Enigmas 7), namely because under every ring there is still another ring. Precisely here lies the link between Baroque thought and Perniola’s philosophy. In fact, Baroque theory conceives reality as sinuous, rich, full, wrapped and enveloped by itself. This perspective should not be understood in negative terms, on the contrary, it implies that the philosopher’s task lies precisely in explaining and developing what is complex, enigmatic, labyrinthine, if not uncanny. Philosophy, according to Perniola, proceeds through a spiral-like movement: it does not investigate its objects of study in their immediacy as if they were simple and transparent objects; rather, it explores them trying to understand their opacity and thickness, namely their richness and complexity. Moreover, here lies a theoretical distinction between postmodern perspective and Perniola’s thought. According to Perniola, when postmodern thinkers define postmodernity by marking it as a passage and a rupture with modernity, they actually carry on the very same argument of modern thinkers against pre-modernity. In other words, both modern and postmodern thinkers share the same attitude of considering themselves within a new era brought about by a fracture with what preceded them. The paradox—underlined by Perniola—is that postmodernity can be considered as a new epoch only insofar as it is not understood as a break with the past, but as a minimal shift, a transition, a transit[1].

 

Reality, according to this view, cannot be understood in terms of polar oppositions (such as true / false, substance / appearance), but as a dynamic set of never-ending micro-changes. Instead of judging reality through the meter of an ideal truth (eternally fixed), reality itself should be understood in its continuum of mutations and variations, namely in its perennial transit. The very idea of a substantial truth, Perniola argues, mystifies the labyrinthine nature of reality by simplifying it in a once-and-for-all formula: “knowledge is not simply the revelation of a secret, nor the illumination of something that was obscure, nor lastly the expounding of a concept given a priori, but the drawing out, the unwinding, the ex-pression of something that is tangled, wound up, gathered in” (Enigmas 5). It is no accident that one of the recurrent themes in Perniola’s works (20th Century Aesthetics; Art and Its Shadow; Enigmas; Ritual Thinking; Sobre el pensar barroco; The Sex Appeal of the Inorganic) is the Baroque period, as it fundamentally mirrors a declination of the transit: from a Baroque perspective, in fact, the world teems with matter coiling, writhing, tangling and developing on itself, exploiting its own inexhaustible subtlety and richness. Importantly, here also lies the post-nihilistic tonality of Perniola’s overall thought. His thought does not deal with Being or Nothingness, but, more modestly and at the same time more complexly, with the concept of “something”. If the world exists, Perniola writes commenting on Leibniz, it is not because it is the best one, “it is rather the other way round: it is the best because it exists, because it is what there is” (Enigmas 9). This world is made of endless combinations of “something” (and never monolithic entities), for which one thing is susceptible of becoming-something-else. This section focused on the relation between the transit and the spatial element (reality as a full inexhaustible presence); the following one will deal with the temporal experience of the transit.

 

transit and different repetition

The concept of transit is influenced by a series of philosophies and thinkers who have developed the notion of repetition. Perniola links together Stoic thought, Roman religiosity, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Freud, Kubler, and Klossowski. Despite the historical (but also conceptual) gaps between them, Perniola individuates a common thread: the notion of “different repetition”. To have a closer understanding, Nietzschean philosophy will be addressed in this paper. There are two main reasons for choosing the German philosopher. First of all, Perniola himself relates Nietzschean thought with the transit (Transiti16-20; La societàdei simulacri48-51); secondly, Nietzsche can be considered among the leading modern philosophers to have delved into the very experience of transit. His entire philosophy can be considered atopical, together with a thinking attitude of “different through the same” which permeates his work (what Deleuze called the “difference through repetition”). The key concepts to understand how Nietzsche can be considered a transit-thinker and—more importantly—what typology of temporality the transit implies, are “amor fati” (love of fate) and “eternal return”.

 

Perniola argues that the notion of transit is affirmed in the Nietzschean concept of amor fati, as by loving one’s own fate, life is experienced in its “present-ness” and availability. On the contrary, metaphysics privileges a time that has yet to come (the world beyond the world, that is, the ideal). The objects of Nietzschean critique are the great metaphysical narratives: morality, Christianity, truth, substance. These narratives essentially imply an entry into an ideal dimension, detached from reality and its actuality. In other words, they attempt to fully mould reality, while also emptying it by means of creating a “world beyond the world”—that is, a product of the human mind disguised as eternally existing and true. If the concept of “ideal” orients an individual’s life, this means that this very individual shapes his/her life around how things should be and not on how things are. Ultimately, at the very rise of each metaphysic, an “ought” (Sollen) judgment arises too. According to Nietzsche, this imperative dictating how things ought to be produces an unfixable distance between human beings and their own lives, and between thought and action. This distance emerges because for Nietzsche life is an unceasing becoming in which there is no place for a fixed conceptual entity. Thus, an imperative regarding how things ought to be, in his perspective, is an arbitrary crystallization that can only pervert the movement of life itself. Metaphysics, subsequent to this argument, is at its very core nihilistic. In fact, to judge reality according to an “ought” implicitly corresponds to a declaration of powerlessness over reality itself: This super reality is nihilistic in its very substance, because it knows very well that it cannot be affirmed and maintained at a factual, empirical, vital level: it sells itself for ideal because it is not real, it poses something beyond because it has no strength to be here and now, it speaks of a transcendent or future life because it was defeated in the only existing one. (Transiti17)

 

At odds with this perspective there is Perniola’s concept of amor fati borrowed from Nietzsche and defined as the “experience of unconditional and passionate loyalty to what is” (Transiti19, italics mine). Nonetheless, in what terms should the experience of amor fati be understood? On the one hand, through amor fati the past is appropriated by the choice of its infinite repetition; on the other hand, life is not procrastinated into a time that is yet to come (an ideal world, a utopia, a paradise…). However, Amor fati should not be understood as a fatalistic law dominating history, or a theological assumption for which one should passively adapt to life’s events provided that there is a God behind Fate or Providence: it corresponds, instead, to an actively chosen lifestyle, which sees life as an experience of endless affirmation. Several questions may arise here: how can one “passionately” affirm events or things that he/she normally despises? How can sadness, death, misery and unhappiness be accepted and “chosen” in one’s own present? How can one love, and not merely bear, the necessary of life? Developing the concept of eternal return, which is strictly connected to amor fati, might be of help.

 

Eternal return is linked to a reconsideration of time, especially of its understanding as a linear configuration, where three main moments can be clearly marked out: past, present and future. These three moments are marked by their mutual difference and by their continued deprivation. The difference indicates the resolution of each event in its uniqueness, so what one experiences now, as far as one can try to repeat it, will be experienced one time only. Deprivation then follows, since all accomplished actions, once acted, are lost in a past, so to speak, already remote “ontologically”. The eternal return is at odds with this perspective. It is the thought of the possibility of a circular time, that is, of the time that preserves itself and which perpetually shows the same combinations of events.

 

Among the interpretations provided on this notion, the one elaborated by Gilles Deleuze will be highlighted in this section. Deleuze’s argument sets apart the cosmological-probabilistic perspective, that in a finite space, given an infinite time, all possible combinations are eternally reverting, making the return a process identical to itself. This perspective, Deleuze writes, is reinforced by the fact that Nietzsche, in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, gave two different expositions of the eternal return: One regards a sick Zarathustra, the other, a convalescent, almost healed Zarathustra. What makes Zarathustra sick is the very idea of the cycle: the idea that Everything returns, that the Same returns, and that everything returns to the same. […] What happened from the moment Zarathustra is convalescent? […] Zarathustra understands the identity “eternal Return-Being selective”. How could what is reactive and nihilistic come back, how could the negative come back, since eternal return is the being that can be predicated only for the affirmation, for the becoming in action? […] Eternal Return is Repetition; but the Repetition that selects, the Repetition that saves (Nietzsche 39-40).

 

Deleuze means that Zarathustra himself criticizes the idea of the eternal return at first, as it was conceived by his travel companions—the eagle and the snake—since they reduced it to a banal “organ song”, namely to a sterile and identical repetition of what happens. On the other hand, this idea would not be consistent with the discourse on the transvaluation of values, for then the last man, Christian morality, metaphysics and, not least, nihilism would all return. Eternal return is instead “selective”, both as thought and as being: as thought, since all one wants is wanted according to amor fati. On the other hand, it is selective as being, since only what can be affirmed comes back. Deleuze compares the eternal return to a spinning wheel, which, turning faster and faster because of centrifugal force, expels from its centre all that contradicts its rotation. The being expels from itself, so to speak, all that contradicts its affirmation. Nihilism and reactive forces are encountered only once, since they return transformed from the eternal return’s centrifugal wheel. As Daniela Angelucci points out: “this repetition that saves us is a choice, a selective act, a staging of an element that turns out, however, each time moved, masked, different, without there being an original principle, a final term of the series” (“Situazione e ripetizione” 47). The “heaviest burden” Nietzsche writes about in The Gay Science consists of engraving the instant with the seal of eternity, for it is only by deciding to live again every moment as it has been that the past does not crush man under its unbearable weight. Only the transformation of each “It was” into “I wanted it thus”, keeps the possibility of the eternal return from being the most terrifying of possibilities. It is precisely for these reasons that Nietzsche defined the doctrine of the eternal return of the same as “the highest formula of affirmation that could ever be attained” (Ecce Homo67). This affirmation consists precisely in the ability to bestow value also on repellent objects. Only in this way, according to Nietzsche, it is possible to make things beautiful: I want to learn more and more how to see what is necessary in things as what is beautiful in them thus I will be one of those who make things beautiful. Amor fati: let that be my love from now on! I do not want to wage war against ugliness. I do not want to accuse; I do not even want to accuse the accusers. Let looking away be my only negation! And, all in all and on the whole: some day I want only to be a Yes-sayer! (The Gay Science157)

 

It is crucial to understand that this statement should not be read with a vitalistic emphasis. The affirmation highlighted goes together with the (different) repetition brought about by the choice of eternal return. This repetition, according to Perniola, leads closer to a ritual thinking than to a vitalistic one. Through repetition, the formal element is preserved, which implies continuation, prosecution, transmission. On the contrary, Perniola considers vitalism nihilistic and iconoclastic as in its effort to satisfy the drives and the instincts of the individual, it dooms each form into dissolution. What Perniola suggests is that in the traditional philosophical dichotomy between form and life, Nietzsche has to be understood within the former. Precisely in this link between form, different repetition and rituality, Nietzschean thought meets Perniola’s concept of transit. Maintaining the same conceptual register, transit is a philosophy of the present but it is not vitalistic. That is to say, it does not imply an acephalous and unoriented present where the individual lets him/herself go to his/her desires and impulses. It is not a hedonistic present in which insatiable hunger for pleasure guides existence. On the contrary, the present of the transit, through amor fati, is loaded with the past which is always “redeemed” by a choice of the will. This choice consists in appropriating one’s own entire past; if all the past is “ours”, nothing can happen which does not belong to us. Indeed, it is through this attitude towards existence that, according to Perniola, one can master his/her own condition.

 

The philosophy of the transit, elaborated by Perniola, is a philosophy of the present and of the presence, precisely because it does not deal with metaphysics and eternal ideals but with earthly historical phenomena. In other words—as was already pointed out in the first paragraph—it does not privilege a time that has yet to come (a utopian future), nor the metaphysic’s conception of time which in turn suspends time by elaborating and believing in timeless truths. On the contrary, the transit allows precisely a dwelling with the present and its atopicality, namely with its richness, availability, presence and depth (in the meaning given to this word
over this section).

 

A philosophy of the present and of the presence as the transit cannot complain about the absence of something, nor regret the lack of anything: it is not in mourning for the loss of some values or ideals, nor of any positive entity. Firstly, because values and ideals have always been too unrealistic and abstract; secondly, because it appropriates, it bears on its shoulders, it makes live in the present what is positive that the past conveys. Contrarily to the image of an empty world, of a kénosis, which would characterize the present society, my research is animated by the image of a full world, of a plèroma, in which everything is at hand. (Transiti3)

 

There is no fatalistic resignation in the transit thought. It is both distant from metaphysics (by avoiding traditional metaphysical concepts such as “ideal”, “truth”, “morality” and so on) and from postmodernism (which praises notions like precarious, ephemeral, flexible—nowadays also the key words of economic neoliberalism). Transit’s thought, on the other hand, draws closer to a present where nothing is missing as everything is present (though folded and wrapped).[2]

 

The philosopher, in addition, being an atopical figure par excellence—according to Perniola—is thus a privileged reader and actor of the contemporary age. In fact, by avoiding ideologies and metaphysical truths, he/she is in the position of “listening” to the present time in its continuous becoming without obstacles (being those disordered affections or pre-given beliefs). In order to understand the uncanny events that happen not only in one’s own life but also in the broader social framework, the philosopher becomes “nothing but an intermediary, a transit zone, a gateway [3] for phenomena that, because they present themselves in an unexpected and unpredictable way, surprise, disturb and astonish” (Enigmas 43). Only in this way can the philosopher be in “direct connection” (presa diretta) with the social-historical reality.

 

conclusion

To sum up, this paper explored Perniola’s notion of transit by developing it in relation to spatiality and temporality (respectively first and second section). In the first section I highlighted Perniola’s re-evaluation of the notion of “depth”, which according to him can be defined as a “stratification of surfaces”. More specifically, by following Perniola’s enquiry over the semantic expansion of the word “depth” back to its Greek and Latin origins, it was shown how this concept only recently gained a meaning connected to the spiritualistic and metaphysical spectrum of “interiority” and “profundity”. Instead, its ancient uses showed how depth can indicate “fullness” and “richness” linked to the earthly world and more generally to effectual reality. Perniola’s concept of transit can be inscribed into this re-evaluation of reality intended as a full available presence. In order to clarify the notion of transit, the second section underlined its connections with Nietzschean philosophy. In particular it revolved around the ideas of amor fati and eternal return. I claim that these should be considered as mutual concepts: the former provides the temporal framework that allows one to move away from the Western-linear conception of time (past, present and future); the latter provides, through the acceptance of this temporality, a propulsive energy through which the very thought of an eternal repetition can be loved (as it will never be a sterile repetition but a different and selective one). The transit can be related to them as it has to be understood as the experience of an “absolute present”, in the etymological sense of ab-solutus, namely “untied” (from linear time) in which nothing is missing because everything is at hand, available. This does not mean that data and events in their immediacy are what to look for. Transit does not imply a vitalistic experience of reality in its immediacy but, as stated in the first section of this paper, it conveys the idea of a deep world made of layers of surfaces. Surface, thus, should not be confused with superficiality, immediacy, or banality. The “polemical objective” of Transiti, as Perniola points out in the Preface to the Second Edition, is the very notion of banality: “the opposite of the transit is the banal, what is perfectly adequate to itself, what is incapable of transformations” (Transiti1). Transiting means going beyond banality without falling into spiritualistic or ideal conceptions by, paradoxically, praising this peculiar perspective of the surface.

 

notes

[1] For this reason Perniola does not actually criticize postmodernity tout court but some perspectives that have developed within it (such as Vattimo and Baudrillard), while his philosophy is closer to other postmodern thinkers (namely Lyotard and Deleuze).

 

[2] It is precisely for these reasons that, according to Perniola, there is a strong connection between society and thought, and this is why the notion of transit can be considered as a sort of helpful lifebelt in the agitated waters of the current world. Perniola explains how the concept of transit “fits” appropriately into contemporary society, better than the key concepts of modernity, namely “tradition” and “innovation”, since they seem to have vanished in a present unquestioning about “neither past nor future, neither a homeland nor a utopia” (Transiti7). Transit is not the diachronicity of a present continuously transcending itself towards the future, but the place where space becomes time in the unlimited availability of presence. The orbital centre of contemporary experience should then be localized in the present. Internet developments provide an indispensable framework for placing the transit experience inside contemporaneity. Massimo Di Felice’s research investigates precisely Perniola’s notion of transit and its contribution to a new theory of network ecologies (see Paesaggi post-urbani).

 

[3] In English in the original text.

Bio

Enea Bianchi is PhD scholar at the National University of Ireland, Galway (2016—). He earned both his BA and MA in Theoretical Philosophy at the University of Rome Tor Vergata with a thesis on the becoming of artistic objects in George Kubler (2013) and over the emotional capitalism studied by Eva Illouz (2015). He is part of the editorial board of the peer reviewed journal of aesthetics and cultural studies Ágalma (www.agalmarivista.org). He is member of the research group “The Philosophy and Practice of Objects / Things” (NUI Galway: https://www.nuigalway.ie/philosophy-practice-objects-things). He has held conferences on contemporary aesthetics in Brasil, Peru, Ireland, Poland and in several Italian cities. His articles are published in Italian and international academic journals. [enea.bianchi@nuigalway.ie]

Bibliography

Angelucci, D. (2015) “Situazione e ripetizione. Debord e Deleuze.” Lebenswelt 6: 44-52.

Deleuze, G. (1965) Nietzsche (Paris: PUF).

Di Felice, M. (2010) Paesaggi post-urbani: la fine dell’esperienza urbana e le forme comunicative dell’abitare (Milan: Bevivino).

Hickman, M. L. (1978) “Visions of the Floating World.” MFA Bulletin76: 4-33.

Nietzsche, F. W.:

–     (2001)The Gay Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

–     (2004) Ecce Homo (New York: Algora).

 

Perniola, M.:

–     (1985) Transiti. Come si va dallo stesso allo stesso (Bologna: Cappelli).

–     (1995) Enigmas. The Egyptian Moment in Society and Art (London-New York: Verso).

–     (2001) Ritual Thinking. Sexuality, Death, World (New York: Humanity Books).

–      (2004) Art and Its Shadow (London-New York: Continuum).

–     (2011) La società dei simulacri (Milan: Mimesis).

–     (2013a) “Per una rivalutazione della nozione di profondità.” Agalma 25: 93-99.

–     (2013b) 20th Century Aesthetics. Towards a Theory of Feeling (London-New York: Bloomsbury).

–     (2014) Sobre el pensar barroco (Lima: Instituto Italiano de Cultura de Lima).

–     (2017) The Sex Appeal of the Inorganic (London-New York: Bloomsbury).

error: Contact artist for permissions.